Chapter 7 – The Law and Ethics of Female Genital Cutting




Chapter 7 The Law and Ethics of Female Genital Cutting


Arianne Shahvisi and Brian D. Earp



Introduction


Nontherapeutic female genital cutting (FGC) typically conjures associations of gender oppression and child abuse in the Western imagination. More commonly described as ‘female genital mutilation’ or ‘FGM’, such cutting has been roundly condemned and legislated against [1]. Yet FGM/C is not exclusively a practice of the Other, as is often assumed. In Western countries, the demand for a range of surgical procedures collectively known as female genital cosmetic surgery (FGCS) is rising [2], as women – and, increasingly, teenage girls [3] – pursue a perceived aesthetic ideal identified with ‘designer vaginas’, including petite clitoral hoods, non-protruding labia, and pre-pubescent hairlessness, apparently modelled on exemplars from pornography [4]. Moreover, some forms of medically unnecessary cosmetic or ‘normalising’ surgery performed on intersex children before an age of consent – such as ‘feminising’ cliteroplasty to reduce the size of healthy, albeit larger than average clitorises [5] – are consistent with Western legal definitions of female genital mutilation, but are largely accepted and still regularly performed [6].


A word on terminology. As ‘mutilation’ is a value-laden term, indicating intentional disfigurement or damage, we consider that its use (a) fails to accurately reflect the motivations of communities within which the class of relevant practices is common (no loving parents seek to mutilate their child), and (b) tends to prefigure the debate, introducing moral biases that are not imposed on analogous forms of non-therapeutic genital cutting which are more familiar in Western contexts, such as FGCS or male circumcision (see Box 7.1), both of which are typically picked out by more neutral descriptors. We therefore favour the terms ‘female genital cutting’ (FGC), ‘female genital cosmetic surgery’ (FGCS) and, where applicable, ‘male genital cutting’ (MGC) or male circumcision, and we will use these terms throughout the chapter. Where it is necessary to use the term ‘FGM’, for example, when referencing the activist/advocacy literature devoted to the elimination of such practices, it will appear in scare quotes to draw attention to its disfavoured status among scholars of genital cutting [79].


In the second section, we describe the different varieties of female genital cutting, focusing on the differences and commonalities between (a) purportedly ‘mutilating’ forms of FGC and (b) Western-style FGCS. The third section interrogates the law in the United Kingdom (and other Western contexts) in relation to each class of procedure. The fourth section highlights the inconsistencies arising from the differential legislative approaches, while the fifth section explores some of the problematic assumptions that underwrite these inconsistencies. The sixth section concludes.



Varieties of Genital Cutting


According to the World Health Organization (WHO), ‘female genital mutilation’ refers to any procedure “involving partial or total removal of the external female genitalia or other injury to the female genital organs for non-medical reasons” [10]. The term therefore covers a loose assemblage of different interventions, carried out by different groups for different reasons in different settings, ranging from a prick to the clitoral hood (which does not remove tissue and is thus less invasive than male circumcision; see Box 7.1) to the excision of the external clitoris followed by suturing of the vaginal opening (known as infibulation). These interventions may occur in a hospital setting or a rural village; they may be carried out by a medical practitioner or a medically untrained ritual provider; they may be performed with sterile instruments and anaesthesia or with a septic tool and no pain control whatsoever [34]. As noted, we will use ‘female genital cutting’ (FGC) to refer to all such non-therapeutic procedures – nontherapeutic in the sense that they are imposed on healthy genitalia and are not intended to treat a recognised disease nor are required to preserve or restore functionality (sexual, reproductive, urinary or otherwise). In practice, FGC almost always involves the clinically unnecessary modification of vulvar tissue in order to adhere to perceived religious or cultural norms or ideals.




Box 7.1 Comparison to Male Genital Cutting


Non-therapeutic male genital cutting (MGC) ranges from ritual pricking (e.g., hatafat dam brit), to piercing, scraping the inside of the urethra, bloodletting, shaft scarring and/or foreskin slitting (among, e.g., various ethnic groups in Papua New Guinea) [11], to circumcision as it is traditionally performed on male newborns in Judaism and generally in the United States (tearing of the membrane that fuses the immature foreskin to the head of the penis followed by excision of the majority of the foreskin) [12], to metzitzah b’peh (the same followed by direct oral suction of the wound, risking herpes infection, performed on more than 3,000 babies in New York City each year within the ultra-Orthodox Jewish community) [7], to non-sterilised, un-anaesthetised circumcisions performed in the bush during rites of passage in Eastern and Southern Africa [13], to highly traumatic mass cutting of pre-teen boys carried out on school tables in the Philippines (tuli) [14], to forced circumcision of men following political conflict in various countries [15], to subincision (slicing open the underside of the penis lengthwise, often through to the urethra) in Aboriginal Australia [16], to involuntary castration (now rare but occasionally documented among the hijras of India). The extent of cutting, tools used, skill of the practitioner, age of the initiate and so on vary widely across circumstances, leading to a heterogeneous risk profile both within and across types. There is also considerable variation in associated social and symbolic meanings (e.g., sealing a divine covenant, punishing an enemy, mimicking menstruation, proving oneself as a man, basis for marriageability, perceived hygiene, ritual purification, conformity to peer pressure, etc.) as well as physical context (e.g., sometimes medicalised, often not), depending on the group in question.


The most common form of MGC is circumcision. Male circumcision involves the partial or total removal of the foreskin of the penis – an elastic sleeve of erogenous tissue that normally covers and protects the glans – occasionally to address a medical problem, but most often for ethnoreligious or cultural reasons [17]. In Western countries the surgery is typically performed on healthy newborn babies or young male children as part of a medicalised birth custom, as in the United States [18], or in the context of a religious ritual, for example, among practicing Muslims and Jews. Such non-therapeutic circumcision of infant males is regarded as legal throughout the Global North, with few restrictions or exceptions [19].


Supporters of circumcision tend to view the procedure as relatively harmless – except in the case of ‘botched’ operations – possibly owing to a lack of awareness of the anatomical properties of the excised tissue (if the tissue itself has value, its sheer removal is a harm) [20]. Increasingly, men who were circumcised in infancy or early childhood, that is, before they were old enough to give or withhold their informed consent, are voicing distress and opposition to the surgery, often citing a lack of personal choice concerning an irreversible alteration to their most private sexual anatomy [21]. In addition to this perceived violation of their genital autonomy, there are also inherent (or highly probable) effects of early circumcision that some such men regard as deleterious. These include the presence of scar tissue and associated discoloration, inability to engage in sexual acts requiring foreskin motility [22], elimination of the parts of the penis most sensitive to light touch [23] and irritation and possible altered sensitivity of the glans.


Common side effects include meatal stenosis (pathological narrowing of the urethral opening) [24], bleeding, infections and incomplete skin removal requiring revision surgery. Additional side effects of unknown frequency include painful erections due to excessive skin removal, partial or complete amputation of the organ due to surgical error, urinary problems, fistulae, skin bridges and cysts [25]. Finally, death is a possible outcome: in the United States, early deaths following circumcision in clinical settings occur at a rate of approximately 1 for every 50,000 circumcisions [26]. In rural settings, such as among the Xhosa of South Africa, deaths as well as penile amputations are far more common: between 2008 and 2014, more than half a million Xhosa boys were hospitalised due to botched circumcisions in the Eastern Cape alone, while between 2006 and 2010 there were 269 recorded deaths among this group and 146 penile amputations [27, 28].


In settings where circumcision is relatively common, such as the United States, prophylactic health benefits are often cited in support of the practice [29]. However, the evidence is contested and is associated primarily with adult, voluntary circumcision in sub-Saharan Africa, not newborn circumcision in economically developed regions with advanced health care systems [30]. In any case, the claimed health benefits can be achieved non-surgically through, e.g., safe sex practices and basic hygiene. Accordingly, the vast majority of international health authorities to have issued formal statements on the health benefits and risks associated with newborn and early childhood male circumcision have concluded that the benefits do not outweigh the risks [31]. Even if they did, however, removing healthy tissue as prophylaxis without consent is not automatically morally acceptable. Consider that performing non-consensual mastectomies on adolescent girls with high-risk genetic profiles in order to guard against future breast cancer would not be tolerated. Similarly, neonatal labiaplasty, though it might conceivably reduce the risk of certain labial cancers or other such problems, is not seriously entertained as a means of health promotion [32]. Although prophylactic tonsillectomies were once common, they are no longer regularly performed; moreover, the tonsils, in contrast to the genitals, are not a visually prominent, psycho-sexually significant external organ. Among ethicists and legal scholars, it is now increasingly argued that male infants and young boys, just like female infants and young girls, have a strong moral interest in having their genital integrity preserved until they are old enough to make an informed, personal decision [33].


Table 7.1 shows the extent of the similarities between the set of practices described by the WHO as ‘FGM’ and those more commonly described as FGCS. As has been noted elsewhere [35], genital cutting procedures are diverse, falling on a wide spectrum of severity, in part because the motivations for the procedures – both conscious and unconscious, historical and contemporary – are likewise diverse. Some groups, for example, are openly committed to tempering the sexual desires of women, as is apparent in many contexts throughout Egypt, where clitoridectomy (partial or total removal of the external clitoris) is common [36]. In other contexts, the procedure marks a transition from childhood to adulthood and may have little to do with reducing sexual desire or exerting sexual control [37]. In still others, such as among the Muslim Malay population of southern Thailand, both boys and girls are subjected to genital cutting as a form of ritual purification as well as to symbolise full acceptance into the Islamic community. For their part, the boys have their foreskins removed in a public ceremony between the ages of 7 and 12, while the girls experience a ‘prick’ to the clitoral hood shortly after birth [38, 39]. Similar cutting occurs among the Dawoodi Bohra sect of Shia Islam, whose followers are concentrated in Gujarat, India, and Karachi, Pakistan: the boys are circumcised, and the girls – in the typical case – have part of their clitoral hood cut or removed in a practice known as khatna, with stated reasons for both kinds of cutting ranging from ‘religious purposes’ to ‘physical hygiene and cleanliness’ [40].




Table 7.1 Comparing ‘FGM’ and FGCS









































‘FGM’ FGCS
Procedures and typology Type I: Alterations of the clitoris, within which type 1a is the partial or total removal of the clitoral hood, and type 1b is the partial or total removal of the clitoral hood and the (external portion of the)a clitoris. Alterations of the clitoris, including clitoral reshaping [42], clitoral unhooding [43], and clitoridectomy or cliteroplasty [44] (also common in “intersex” surgeries) [5, 6].
Type II: Alterations of the labia, within which type IIa is the partial or total removal of the labia minora, type IIb is the partial or total removal of the labia minora and/or the (external)a clitoris and type IIc is the partial or total removal of the labia minora, labia majora and (external)a clitoris. Alterations of the labia, including trimming of the labia minora and/or majora, also known as ‘labiaplasty’ [42, 43].
Type III: Alterations of the vaginal opening, within which type IIIa is the partial or total removal and appositioning of the labia minora, and type IIIb is the partial or total removal and appositioning of the labia majora, both as ways of narrowing the vaginal opening. Alterations of the vaginal opening, typified by narrowing of the vaginal opening, variously known as ‘vaginal tightening’, ‘vaginal rejuvenation’ [45] or ‘hymen repair’ [46].
Type IV: Miscellaneous, including piercing, pricking, scraping and cauterisation. Miscellaneous, including piercing [47], tattooing [48] and liposuction [49].
Example high-prevalence geographies Depending on the procedure: Somalia, Sierra Leone, Guinea, Djibouti, Egypt, Mali, Sudan, Senegal, Eritrea, Ethiopia, Mauritania, Liberia, Burkina Faso, Gambia, Guinea Bissau, Kenya, Nigeria, Chad, Cote d’Ivoire and concomitant diaspora communities [50]. North America, Australia, Europe [51].
Actor Traditional practitioner, midwife, clinical worker or paramedic, surgeon. Surgeon, tattoo artist, body piercer.
Age at which performed Depending on the procedure/community: typically around puberty, but ranging from infancy to adulthood [32]. Typically in adulthood, but increasingly on adolescent girls [3]; intersex surgeries (e.g., cliteroplasty) more common in infancy, but ranging through adolescence and adulthood [52].
Legal status in the UK and similar regimes Unlawful Lawful




a The WHO wrongly equates the external portion of the clitoris (i.e., the part that protrudes outside the body) with the entire clitoris, thereby diminishing the anatomical and sexual significance of the latter. Most of the clitoris, including the majority of its erectile tissues and structures necessary for orgasm, is underneath the superficial skin layer of the body – like an iceberg – and therefore cannot be removed without major surgery (which does not occur in any recognised form of ‘FGM’). This fact may explain why sexual pleasure and orgasm are reported at higher than expected rates in women who have experienced various forms of genital cutting [53].


The WHO collects all such (female) practices together under the banner of ‘FGM’ [41]. Although some nuance is introduced through seemingly arbitrary divisions into types and sub-types, the WHO typology is not able to ground a principled distinction between (typically African, Middle Eastern or Southeast Asian) so-called mutilations and (chiefly European and North American) so-called cosmetic genital procedures. In the second column of Table 7.1, we present a parallel typology of practices which are standard within FGCSs. The table is organised to exhibit the commonalities between the component practices.


Table 7.1 shows that for each component of the ‘FGM’ typology, there is a close analogue within the FGCS typology. Alterations of the clitoris, labia and vaginal opening are observed in both sets of practices, with considerable variation both between and across cases as to the degree of tissue damage or removal. Instead of using umbrella terms such as ‘FGM’ or FGCS, then, it is likely to be more illuminating in most cases to be specific. Thus, one should refer to (1) particular procedures (e.g., labiaplasty, cliteridectomy, hoodectomy, infibulation); (2) the extent of the procedure, along with the means by which it is carried out – i.e., with which instruments and how skilfully – and the associated risk/benefit profile (both medical and non-medical); and (3) the relevant context: physical, psychological and social/symbolic. As it stands, the terms ‘FGM’ and FGCS are proposed as stable categories not on the basis of the acts that actually fall within them, but instead by the perceived reasons for undertaking those acts (e.g., ‘non-medical reasons’, ‘to oppress women’ and so on).


That said, there are some differences between the two categories. The first is that the practices known as ‘FGM’ are generally not performed in a regulated medical setting (although they are increasingly being performed in medicalised settings in the communities in which they are common and customary) [54], while those within the FGCS typology are usually performed by trained professionals in medical or similar facilities (although there are growing concerns about a lack of regulation) [55].


A second potential difference concerns the age at which the cutting is typically performed – i.e., usually minor girls for ‘FGM’, usually adult women for FGCS – but there is overlap here as well. First, in many African societies, female and male genital cutting ceremonies constitute the very ritual by which adult status is conferred in the community, which complicates the question of consent as well as adult/child designations [56]. Second, staying just within the USA, UK and other Western contexts, non-therapeutic genital cutting – e.g., cosmetic labiaplasty – is increasingly performed on female children and adolescents well before the age of legal majority [57].


The final difference is their status in law: in Western countries FGM of any type is illegal (in the UK and Australia, this is true regardless of the age at which it is performed), while in these same countries, FGCS is treated as legal despite technically meeting the same criteria [58].



The Status of the Law


In this chapter, we take UK law as a case study. However, similar laws apply throughout the Western world [59], where increased migration of FGC-prevalent communities, coupled with a growing focus on FGC as a contested site of political attention, have led to pressure to address FGC either in dedicated legislation, or under existing laws.


In England, Wales and Northern Ireland, the FGM Act 2003 holds that “to excise, infibulate, or otherwise mutilate any part of a girl’s labia minora, majora or clitoris” is an offense with a maximum sentence of fourteen years [60]. The legislation has two puzzling features. First, it stipulates that “Girl includes woman” and therefore equates the consent capacities of adult women to those of children. Second, the legislation contains a caveat to permit genital alterations where they are deemed necessary to the “mental health” of a person, while noting that it is “immaterial” for purpose of making such assessments whether the person requesting the alteration “or any other person believes that the operation is required as a matter of custom or ritual.”


These rather confusing qualifications were evidently inserted to ring-fence access to FGCS, by portraying such procedures as necessary to the mental health of some women (as judged by their cosmetic surgeons), while preventing ‘traditional’ FGC, which is more readily interpreted as being performed for reasons that qualify as customary or ritualistic, from slipping through under the mental health clause. Dustin [61] suggests that the cosmetic surgery lobby may have played a key role in securing the future of FGCS when the legislation was being drafted.


Yet one could argue that FGCS also qualifies as being motivated by custom or ritual. As noted by Crouch and colleagues, it is “difficult to see how FGCS could be anything other than cultural” [62]. For as Edwards argues, “any woman’s choice to have a procedure on her genitals cannot be separated from the culture in which this decision is made” [63]. Highly restrictive aesthetic ideals, widespread anatomical ignorance about the range of ‘normal’ appearances for the vulva, marketing campaigns designed to prey on bodily insecurities and normatively questionable social pressures undoubtedly threaten ‘mental health’ and thus play a role in motivating requests for FGCS [64]. In short, “the rationale [for cutting] cannot be separated from cultural associations” regardless of the culture in which it occurs [63].


Similarly, it is plausible that there may be potentially severe adverse consequences to the mental health of a person who is denied FGC if she lives within an FGC-prevalent community, identifies with the practice, regards modified vulvae as normal or beautiful (or unmodified vulvae as abnormal or ugly) [7, 9, 56, 86] and so on. But if, as it seems reasonable to argue, problematic cultural norms or expectations are ultimately to blame for any such psychological anguish – such that the norms and expectations, rather than female bodies, should be changed [46] – they are certainly no less to blame for women’s ‘mental health’ issues in the majority culture, which are used to justify FGCS.


Perhaps the difference in law can be grounded in the fact that FGCS is medically safer than FGC. One might indeed contend that the first is safer under current legislation, as it is usually performed in clinical contexts, while the latter must be performed ‘underground’ in Western countries because it is unlawful. Yet the division is not so tidy. First, in communities where FGC is common, the cutting is often performed in medical settings prior to immigration: according to the WHO, in some FGC-prevalent countries, “one-third or more of women had their daughter subjected to the practice by a trained health professional” [10]. By contrast, Western-style ‘cosmetic’ genital piercing, a legal form of FGCS, typically takes place in a non-clinical environment such as a tattoo parlour and is only minimally regulated [55].


Moreover, depending on the type of cutting, medical training does not guarantee superior skill: for example, in some communities, FGC – similar to MGC performed by a Jewish mohel – is carried out by a highly experienced circumciser for whom the cutting is her primary occupation. Thus, medicalisation per se does not eliminate, nor even necessarily reduce, the risk of complications, as the WHO also notes [10] (but see [65]).


Accordingly, many of the complications and risks are similar for FGC and FGCS where the type (as indicated in Table 7.1) matches. Even where FGCS of various types are performed by a licensed surgeon, the following complications are commonly noted: infection, healing problems, adhesion, dyspareunia, bleeding and effects on sexual pleasure [66]. These are strongly redolent of the sorts of complications that are often described as following from many instances of FGC, though of course, non-clinical environments and instruments, where applicable, may render these complications more likely and more severe [67].


Finally, as noted earlier, the presumed difference between FGC and FGCS in terms of the age at which the cutting takes place is not sufficient to ground such divergent laws: some FGC procedures, such as re-infibulation, are requested by adult women [68], while some FGCS procedures are performed on adolescent girls. Nevertheless, in all Western contexts, ‘FGM’ is unlawful, while FGCS procedures are presumed to be lawful. The ‘mental health’ caveat within UK law in particular exemplifies the difficulty in outlawing one set of procedures while protecting access to a set of procedures that is identical or nearly identical in physical terms. The difference, in the eyes of the law, then seems to rest on certain stereotypes concerning the reason for which the procedure is undertaken, a matter we will take up in the following sections.



Interrogating Inconsistencies


All three of FGCS, FGC and MGC involve the non-therapeutic modification or removal of healthy, erotogenic tissue. While there is a lively debate about the average (net) effects of these practices on health [29, 30, 31, 69] and sexual pleasure [22, 30, 70, 86], what is often lost in such discussions is that no one is an embodied statistical average: genital cutting affects different individuals differently, depending on the type and extent of cutting, whether and what kind of pain control is used, the age at which it is performed, the skill of the practitioner, one’s mind-set going into the cutting – or later reflecting on it or its effects – and so on [71]. Given such vast individual differences, arguably the more pressing question for ethicists working within a Western medico-legal context is whether the person in question can consent to the procedure and thereby exercise bodily autonomy, often characterised as a (human) right [72].


As noted, the capacity of adult women to choose FGC or FGCS is sometimes disputed, often along racial lines, a discussion to which we will return later. But the question of consent is perhaps most salient in the case of children. Supporters of childhood genital cutting note that infants and young children are pre-autonomous and therefore incapable of either giving or withholding their informed consent, not only to genital cutting, but to any significant parental action that affects them [73]. Therefore, they suggest, it is up to the parents to decide whether to cut the child’s genitals. But such cutting is typically irreversible: depriving a child of the opportunity to remain genitally intact is also to deprive the eventual adult of the same opportunity. Plainly, a child’s temporary lack of capacity to make certain informed, mature decisions about the state or condition of their own body does not create a ‘blank cheque’ for parents to authorise whatever permanent body alterations they may choose [74].


Granting this point, some authors argue that the permissibility of a given act of childhood genital cutting – usually presumed to fall somewhere beneath an arbitrary and unspecified threshold of harm [75] – depends on the reason for its performance, that is, the conscious or unconscious motive(s) of the parents or wider community [73]. Some motives, at least for certain kinds of non-therapeutic childhood genital cutting, appear to be regarded as acceptable in Western societies, while other motives are regarded as unacceptable.


For example, discussants who oppose even less physically invasive forms of FGC carried out prior to an age of consent (for example, ritual nicking), while at the same time tolerating or even advocating more physically invasive forms of MGC carried out prior to an age of consent (chiefly, infant male circumcision), tend to base their arguments on the premise that male circumcision is a religious requirement, at least for some groups, while FGC is not. The argument then proceeds to claim that if there is a ‘religious’ motive for childhood genital cutting, then the cutting can be justified, whether morally or legally.


However, the premise is false, so the argument is unsound. First, FGC is very often regarded by its supporters as an explicitly Islamic practice with the same or similar scriptural standing as male circumcision [7, 65]. While it is true that FGC, like MGC, is not mentioned in Koranic scripture, both are noted in the Hadith, a record of the teachings of the Prophet Mohammed. On this basis, some Muslim authorities argue that FGC is in fact obligatory (though this view is far from universal) [76]. Certainly, in Judaism and Christianity, it is widely held that ‘binding’ religious obligations can stem from extra-biblical sources, such as rabbinic commentaries or papal encyclicals: the notion that a practice can only be ‘religious’ if it is grounded in a literal reading of a group’s primary scripture is absurd [65].


Second, male circumcision is often performed for merely ‘cultural’, rather than specifically religious, reasons, and yet it is broadly tolerated even in those cases. Christians in Africa, for instance, often practise infant male circumcision not because they view it as an explicit requirement of their own religion, but rather because the practice is widespread in the communities alongside which they live [77]. In the United States, circumcision of newborn boys is performed mostly in accordance with perceived social and aesthetic norms by those who place no religious stake in the surgery whatsoever, with statements such as “the boy should look like his father” held up as common explanations [18, 78]. Even many Jews who circumcise are atheists or otherwise non-religious, yet choose to continue the tradition for various reasons including a sense of shared history or ethnic identity [79]. In a similar vein, a study in Australia showed that three times as many parents opted to have their newborn son circumcised to continue a ‘family tradition’ than to fulfil a perceived religious obligation [80].


This leads to a dilemma. If male circumcision should be permitted generally and for any reason because in some groups it is regarded as an explicitly religious practice, then relatively more mild forms of FGC that are regarded by some groups as religiously required should be given equal consideration, and should also be tolerated for all groups regardless of the reason. Indeed, some prominent defenders of ritual male circumcision, aware of the existing double standard (see Box 7.1), have recently begun to argue that ‘mild’ forms of FGC should in fact be tolerated in Western law, presumably to ensure that the legal status of male circumcision remains unquestioned [65, 81]. Alternatively, one might argue that male circumcision should be permitted only when it is done for explicitly religious reasons (which would exclude most US American circumcisions, and might also exclude non-religious Jewish and Islamic circumcisions that would otherwise be done for merely ‘cultural’ reasons), in which case, by analogy, only groups that regard FGC as religiously required would be permitted to perform the cutting, and all others disallowed. Finally, one could argue that neither male nor female non-therapeutic childhood genital cutting should be permitted, regardless of the religious motives of the parents [82].


Whichever option one favours, the common emphasis in this discourse on ‘religion’ versus ‘culture’ is telling. The apparent assumption is that religious norms are categorically different from, and more important than, ‘merely’ cultural norms. However, it is not obvious that there is a firm line – whether in practice or conceptually – between what is religious and what is cultural [77], nor is it obvious that one should be elevated above the other as ‘legitimate’ grounds for cutting the genitals of a child [83].




Box 7.2 Double Standards: A Case Study


This apparent double standard is playing out as we write this chapter. Four members of the Dawoodi Bohra, a small Muslim sect with members in Detroit, Michigan, and other US cities, have recently been indicted on charges of ‘Female Genital Mutilation’ – the first such case under federal law in the United States [84]. As even opponents of the practice from within the community acknowledge [40], the form of cutting typically practised by the Bohra on their daughters, namely, pricking or excision of a portion of the hood (foreskin) of the external clitoris – often by a doctor in a clinical setting, as in the Detroit case being prosecuted – is significantly less physically invasive than the form of cutting practised by the very same community on their sons, namely, complete removal of the penile foreskin (circumcision). The two forms of cutting may be done at similar ages, for similar reasons; both are regarded as a religious obligation by the Bohra based on similar readings of the same passages of Muslim scripture (in this case, the Hadith – the sayings of the Prophet Mohammed); and both are referred to with the same word, khatna. Yet, though the male procedure is more severe, only the female procedure has triggered criminal proceedings under federal law [69].


Even more peculiar, the false dichotomy is inconsistently applied. For example, it is often argued that (adult) FGCS is more acceptable than (adult) FGC because the former are not motivated by a strong cultural imperative [85]. That is, FGCS is presented as a procedure which is chosen by those who request it, which makes it at least plausibly permissible, whereas FGC is presented as an obligation for those who request it (by virtue of being a ritual or custom), which then renders it impermissible because it is presumably not ‘freely’ chosen. But if common defences for male circumcision are to be accepted, one could equally hold that since FGC is ‘mandated’ by strong religious or cultural pressures in some groups, it is something that Western societies ought to tolerate, whereas since FGCS is not ‘mandated’ in a similar way, it should not be granted this shortcut to tolerance. Either way, the status quo is incoherent.


Simply put, the reasoning deployed to defend pre-consensual male circumcision and against pre-consensual FGC is sharply at odds with the reasoning deployed to defend adult FGCS and against adult FGC. In the case of motivations for ritual male circumcision, it is commonly argued that the strength of the associated background norm, whether religious or ‘merely’ cultural, is a reason for respecting or tolerating the practice, despite the fact that young male children and especially newborn boys are manifestly incapable of providing their own consent. Yet in the case of FGC, the strength of what is in some communities an equally robust and often highly similar background norm is seen as consent-undermining, not only for female minors but also mature adult women – irrespective of their agency or autonomy as might be demonstrated in other contexts.


On one side, then, we have MGC, one form of which is of great religious significance to some groups, while for others it is ‘merely’ cultural but is not necessarily any less valued. Although it is typically performed on the most intimate part of a child’s body before consent can possibly be given or withheld, it is widely accepted and is permitted by Western law. On the other side, we have FGCS, a set of procedures that have primarily aesthetic value for a small – if growing – number of individuals and are of no religious significance to anyone. They are typically performed on adults who are presumed to be competent to provide their own consent but are also increasingly performed on younger girls with the permission (or at the insistence) of their parents. They, too, are relatively uncontroversial and are permitted by Western law. Then in the middle we have FGC, an anatomically overlapping set of procedures performed at various ages, sometimes on adults or older adolescents who are typically presumed, in this case, to be non-competent to provide consent, but most often on younger girls with the permission (or at the insistence) of their parents. Certain forms are of great religious significance to some groups and have aesthetic value for those who embrace them [86, 87], but all forms are seen as entirely unacceptable, and no form is permitted by Western law.

Only gold members can continue reading. Log In or Register to continue

Stay updated, free articles. Join our Telegram channel

Oct 26, 2020 | Posted by in General Surgery | Comments Off on Chapter 7 – The Law and Ethics of Female Genital Cutting

Full access? Get Clinical Tree

Get Clinical Tree app for offline access