1 Controversies in the ethics of organ transplantation
“Best practice in organ transplantation requires sensitivity to the ethical dimension within clinical situations, fluency in the language of ethical discussion and skill in the practical resolution of ethically complex scenarios.”
Introduction
The history of transplantation is relatively brief at 40–50 years compared with the history of medicine, and the unique processes involved in this branch of medicine continue to surprise and challenge conventional medical and ethical doctrine. Many of the ethical dilemmas surrounding transplantation centre on the twin peaks of procurement and allocation. The questions of ‘how do we get organs’ and ‘who should receive them’ permeate all aspects of transplantation ethics and clinical practice. Indeed, ethics is an important part of medical education as acknowledged by the General Medical Council’s publication Tomorrow’s Doctors, which placed ethics squarely in the core curriculum for medical training so that doctors would be able ‘to understand and analyse ethical problems so as to enable patients, their families, society, and the doctor to have proper regard to such problems in reaching decisions’.1
Systems and principles in medical ethics and bioethics
The ethical basis of Western medicine is characterised by a number of traditions,2 which find expression in codes of practice and in the culture of healthcare workers. Prominent amongst these are the deontological (duty-based) and the utilitarian (consequence-based) traditions.
The deontological tradition3 stresses the duties of practitioners and the rights of patients. Many codes3 of practice, such as the Hippocratic Oath, the Declaration of Geneva and the General Medical Council Statements4 on ‘Duties and Responsibilities of Doctors’, are of this tradition. There is a strand of rational, universalising deliberation within deontology that may, in some circumstances, seem uncompromising and excessively rigid. Clinicians ‘ought’ to act in particular ways because this is ‘right’, often irrespective of the consequences. Any act should be capable of being expressed as a universal law. The great strength of the deontological tradition is its stress on the autonomy of the patient and on the primacy of doctor–patient relationships. It asserts that individuals should always be viewed as ends in themselves, never as means to an end. Its weakness is in application. ‘Absolute’ principles that are contradictory may co-present in particular circumstances (e.g. ‘never cause pain’, ‘always preserve life’ – what if life-saving interventions cause pain?).
On the other hand, the utilitarian tradition3 aspires always to do that which leads to a ‘good’ or ‘best’ outcome. It is commonly paraphrased as ‘Seek the greatest good for the greatest number’. If the ‘right’ action does not lead to the ‘best’ outcome then it should be reviewed or abandoned. The necessity for rationing of healthcare resources brings utilitarian analyses into particular prominence. On occasion, the individual may be the ‘loser’ in the greater scheme of things – a common criticism of this approach.
Both traditions have a strong flavour of universalisation. However, as all ethical analyses ultimately focus on particular cases, the importance of context may well have been understated in the past. Some current intellectual traditions, notably existentialism, situation ethics and postmodernism,3 are less convinced of the existence of general laws/principles that can be applied to particular cases. Rather, they focus on how to solve specific problems as they arise and are open to the insights of other religious, racial, philosophical and cultural traditions. The principal criticism of these traditions is that moral relativism may easily drift into moral anarchy (although, of course, moral absolutism may similarly drift into moral fascism).
Principles
A number of prima facie principles (commonly distilled to four) are widely accepted as forming the bedrock of medical ethics.3,4 As we shall see, in individual cases there is often conflict between the simultaneous adherence to all of these. Depending on the context (and on whether a deontological or utilitarian approach is favoured), a ‘least unsatisfactory’ trade-off between principles must be negotiated or achieved. Skill in identifying and achieving the best balance is that which characterises best practice in dealing with moral dilemmas.
1 Beneficence: doing good3,4
A central tenet of medical ethics is the obligation to strive at all times to do good for the patient. Deontologists view this as a universal moral duty, utilitarians as achieving the universally desired best outcome. It is instructive to reflect upon the secondary obligations that follow from acceptance of this principle. Beneficence demands competence. Accreditation and continuing medical education are central to this, as are elements such as professional development, clinical and basic research, and audit. Transplant programmes with clinical governance processes in place are expressing vigorous adherence to this principle. Communication skills are vital – weighing up possible outcomes is one thing, sharing them with the patient and negotiating choices quite another.
3 Respect for autonomy3–5
Informed consent is central to the doctor–patient relationship. Its definition is difficult – in countries such as Australia and Canada there is a legal duty to provide patients with information that a prudent or reasonable patient, in that patient’s particular circumstances, would wish to know in order to arrive at a decision. In the UK, the amount of information that a reasonable doctor would provide, in that patient’s particular circumstances, is required.6 (However, a court might decide that, in unusual circumstances, failure to disclose certain risks of procedures might be negligent, even if this is accepted practice as attested by a responsible body of medical opinion.) Information about certain possible risks may be retained under so-called therapeutic privilege, if it is honestly felt that this would needlessly harm the patient psychologically (justified by an ‘act’ utilitarian attitude with heavy emphasis on non-maleficence). This privilege cannot be invoked when informed consent to participation in a research study is being obtained – for obvious reasons. No overt or covert pressure to consent should exist. Many guidelines6 exist to help deal with difficulties in obtaining consent.
In the case considered in Box 1.1 it could be argued that transplantation in an individual who has expressed, by his actions, a wish to die is a breach of his autonomy. In general terms, interventions made when patients do not have the capacity to offer consent should follow certain principles. Any advance directives should be consulted; persons with knowledge of the patient’s previous views should be consulted for their insight into the possible choices that the patient might have made were he able to participate. Family cannot consent to any procedure on his behalf, unless there is a legal guardianship in existence. The decision as to how best to proceed should be taken by the doctor with overall responsibility for the case. Choices should be limited to those that are in the patient’s best interests and that least limit the patient’s future choices should he regain the capacity to consent. In this situation the clinicians have used the principle of beneficence to justify the act of transplantation, in the hope that the attempt at self-harm was, at best, accidental or, at worst, not intended to result in death. A utilitarian perspective might argue against transplantation in this situation, giving priority in the allocation of organs to individuals who have unequivocally expressed a desire to live. Alternatively, it could be argued that the circumstances precipitating this act of self-harm are transient or that the normal mental state of the individual may have been temporarily disturbed. This could respond to a change in circumstances or to treatment with appropriate counselling or medications. In this unusual scenario, the reiteration by the patient that he wishes to die, and his refusal to continue with treatment necessary to keep the transplant functional, presents a complex matrix of interaction between differing principles. If he has regained the capacity to consent, then his autonomy must be respected. On the other hand, this should prompt a discussion as to the reasons why the original choice was made. Beneficence and non-maleficence may prompt the clinicians strongly to counsel him to continue with treatment. It should be pointed out (in the spirit of justice) that he has received a scarce resource and that a range of individuals have done their best to make the right choice for him. One might wish to use this as a pragmatic ‘emotional lever’ in the discussion – however, primacy must be given to his autonomy.
Conditional and directed donation
The following scenarios set out a series of events concerning organ donation which challenge ethical principles. These scenarios have been adapted from cases devised by Professor James Neuberger and Mr A. David Mayer of the Queen Elizabeth Hospital Birmingham and are based on actual cases.7,8